Built with Alectryon, running Coq+SerAPI v8.10.0+0.7.0. Coq sources are in this panel; goals and messages will appear in the other. Bubbles () indicate interactive fragments: hover for details, tap to reveal contents. Use Ctrl+↑ Ctrl+↓ to navigate, Ctrl+🖱️ to focus.
Set Warnings "-notation-overridden,-parsing". From LF Require Export IndProp.
"Algorithms are the computational content of proofs." --Robert Harper
We have seen that Coq has mechanisms both for programming,
using inductive data types like nat or list and functions over
these types, and for proving properties of these programs, using
inductive propositions (like even), implication, universal
quantification, and the like. So far, we have mostly treated
these mechanisms as if they were quite separate, and for many
purposes this is a good way to think. But we have also seen hints
that Coq's programming and proving facilities are closely related.
For example, the keyword Inductive is used to declare both data
types and propositions, and → is used both to describe the type
of functions on data and logical implication. This is not just a
syntactic accident! In fact, programs and proofs in Coq are
almost the same thing. In this chapter we will study how this
works.
We have already seen the fundamental idea: provability in Coq is
represented by concrete evidence. When we construct the proof
of a basic proposition, we are actually building a tree of
evidence, which can be thought of as a data structure.
If the proposition is an implication like A → B, then its proof
will be an evidence transformer: a recipe for converting
evidence for A into evidence for B. So at a fundamental level,
proofs are simply programs that manipulate evidence.
Question: If evidence is data, what are propositions themselves?
Answer: They are types!
Look again at the formal definition of the even property.
Suppose we introduce an alternative pronunciation of ":".
Instead of "has type," we can say "is a proof of." For example,
the second line in the definition of even declares that ev_0 : even
0. Instead of "ev_0 has type even 0," we can say that "ev_0
is a proof of even 0."
This pun between types and propositions -- between : as "has type"
and : as "is a proof of" or "is evidence for" -- is called the
Curry-Howard correspondence. It proposes a deep connection
between the world of logic and the world of computation:
propositions ~ types
proofs ~ data values
See Wadler 2015 (in Bib.v) for a brief history and up-to-date exposition.
Many useful insights follow from this connection. To begin with,
it gives us a natural interpretation of the type of the ev_SS
constructor:
This can be read "ev_SS is a constructor that takes two
arguments -- a number n and evidence for the proposition even
n -- and yields evidence for the proposition even (S (S n))."
Now let's look again at a previous proof involving even.
even 4even 4even 2apply ev_0. Qed.even 0
As with ordinary data values and functions, we can use the Print
command to see the proof object that results from this proof
script.
Indeed, we can also write down this proof object directly,
without the need for a separate proof script:
The expression ev_SS 2 (ev_SS 0 ev_0) can be thought of as
instantiating the parameterized constructor ev_SS with the
specific arguments 2 and 0 plus the corresponding proof
objects for its premises even 2 and even 0. Alternatively, we can
think of ev_SS as a primitive "evidence constructor" that, when
applied to a particular number, wants to be further applied to
evidence that that number is even; its type,
forall n, even n -> even (S (S n)),
expresses this functionality, in the same way that the polymorphic
type ∀ X, list X expresses the fact that the constructor
nil can be thought of as a function from types to empty lists
with elements of that type.
We saw in the Logic chapter that we can use function
application syntax to instantiate universally quantified variables
in lemmas, as well as to supply evidence for assumptions that
these lemmas impose. For instance:
even 4apply (ev_SS 2 (ev_SS 0 ev_0)). Qed. (* ################################################################# *)even 4
The proof objects we've been discussing lie at the core of how
Coq operates. When Coq is following a proof script, what is
happening internally is that it is gradually constructing a proof
object -- a term whose type is the proposition being proved. The
tactics between Proof and Qed tell it how to build up a term
of the required type. To see this process in action, let's use
the Show Proof command to display the current state of the proof
tree at various points in the following tactic proof.
even 4even 4even 2even 0apply ev_0.Qed.
At any given moment, Coq has constructed a term with a
"hole" (indicated by ?Goal here, and so on), and it knows what
type of evidence is needed to fill this hole.
Each hole corresponds to a subgoal, and the proof is
finished when there are no more subgoals. At this point, the
evidence we've built stored in the global context under the name
given in the Theorem command.
Tactic proofs are useful and convenient, but they are not
essential: in principle, we can always construct the required
evidence by hand, as shown above. Then we can use Definition
(rather than Theorem) to give a global name directly to this
evidence.
Definition ev_4''' : even 4 :=
ev_SS 2 (ev_SS 0 ev_0).
All these different ways of building the proof lead to exactly the
same evidence being saved in the global environment.
Exercise: 2 stars, standard (eight_is_even)
even 8(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.even 8Admitted.even 8
☐
(* ################################################################# *)
In Coq's computational universe (where data structures and
programs live), there are two sorts of values with arrows in their
types: constructors introduced by Inductively defined data
types, and functions.
Similarly, in Coq's logical universe (where we carry out proofs),
there are two ways of giving evidence for an implication:
constructors introduced by Inductively defined propositions,
and... functions!
For example, consider this statement:
forall n : nat, even n -> even (4 + n)forall n : nat, even n -> even (4 + n)n:natH:even neven (4 + n)n:natH:even neven (S (S (S (S n))))n:natH:even neven (S (S n))apply H. Qed.n:natH:even neven n
What is the proof object corresponding to ev_plus4?
We're looking for an expression whose type is ∀ n, even n →
even (4 + n) -- that is, a function that takes two arguments (one
number and a piece of evidence) and returns a piece of evidence!
Here it is:
Definition ev_plus4' : forall n, even n -> even (4 + n) :=
fun (n : nat) => fun (H : even n) =>
ev_SS (S (S n)) (ev_SS n H).
Recall that fun n ⇒ blah means "the function that, given n,
yields blah," and that Coq treats 4 + n and S (S (S (S n)))
as synonyms. Another equivalent way to write this definition is:
Definition ev_plus4'' (n : nat) (H : even n) : even (4 + n) := ev_SS (S (S n)) (ev_SS n H).
When we view the proposition being proved by ev_plus4 as a
function type, one interesting point becomes apparent: The second
argument's type, even n, mentions the value of the first
argument, n.
While such dependent types are not found in conventional
programming languages, they can be useful in programming too, as
the recent flurry of activity in the functional programming
community demonstrates.
Notice that both implication (→) and quantification (∀)
correspond to functions on evidence. In fact, they are really the
same thing: → is just a shorthand for a degenerate use of
∀ where there is no dependency, i.e., no need to give a
name to the type on the left-hand side of the arrow:
forall (x:nat), nat
= forall (_:nat), nat
= nat -> nat
For example, consider this proposition:
Definition ev_plus2 : Prop :=
forall n, forall (E : even n), even (n + 2).
A proof term inhabiting this proposition would be a function
with two arguments: a number n and some evidence E that n is
even. But the name E for this evidence is not used in the rest
of the statement of ev_plus2, so it's a bit silly to bother
making up a name for it. We could write it like this instead,
using the dummy identifier _ in place of a real name:
Definition ev_plus2' : Prop :=
forall n, forall (_ : even n), even (n + 2).
Or, equivalently, we can write it in more familiar notation:
Definition ev_plus2'' : Prop :=
forall n, even n -> even (n + 2).
In general, "P → Q" is just syntactic sugar for
"∀ (_:P), Q".
(* ################################################################# *)
If we can build proofs by giving explicit terms rather than
executing tactic scripts, you may be wondering whether we can
build programs using tactics rather than explicit terms.
Naturally, the answer is yes!
nat -> natn:natnatn:natnatapply n. Defined.
Notice that we terminate the Definition with a . rather than
with := followed by a term. This tells Coq to enter proof
scripting mode to build an object of type nat → nat. Also, we
terminate the proof with Defined rather than Qed; this makes
the definition transparent so that it can be used in computation
like a normally-defined function. (Qed-defined objects are
opaque during computation.)
This feature is mainly useful for writing functions with dependent
types, which we won't explore much further in this book. But it
does illustrate the uniformity and orthogonality of the basic
ideas in Coq.
(* ################################################################# *)
Inductive definitions are powerful enough to express most of the
connectives we have seen so far. Indeed, only universal
quantification (with implication as a special case) is built into
Coq; all the others are defined inductively. We'll see these
definitions in this section.
Module Props. (* ================================================================= *)
To prove that P ∧ Q holds, we must present evidence for both
P and Q. Thus, it makes sense to define a proof object for P
∧ Q as consisting of a pair of two proofs: one for P and
another one for Q. This leads to the following definition.
Module And. Inductive and (P Q : Prop) : Prop := | conj : P -> Q -> and P Q. End And.
Notice the similarity with the definition of the prod type,
given in chapter Poly; the only difference is that prod takes
Type arguments, whereas and takes Prop arguments.
This similarity should clarify why destruct and intros
patterns can be used on a conjunctive hypothesis. Case analysis
allows us to consider all possible ways in which P ∧ Q was
proved -- here just one (the conj constructor).
Similarly, the split tactic actually works for any inductively
defined proposition with exactly one constructor. In particular,
it works for and:
forall P Q : Prop, P /\ Q <-> Q /\ Pforall P Q : Prop, P /\ Q <-> Q /\ PP, Q:PropP /\ Q <-> Q /\ PP, Q:PropP /\ Q -> Q /\ PP, Q:PropQ /\ P -> P /\ QP, Q:PropP /\ Q -> Q /\ PP, Q:PropHP:PHQ:QQ /\ PP, Q:PropHP:PHQ:QQP, Q:PropHP:PHQ:QPapply HQ.P, Q:PropHP:PHQ:QQapply HP.P, Q:PropHP:PHQ:QPP, Q:PropQ /\ P -> P /\ QP, Q:PropHP:QHQ:PP /\ QP, Q:PropHP:QHQ:PPP, Q:PropHP:QHQ:PQapply HQ.P, Q:PropHP:QHQ:PPapply HP. Qed.P, Q:PropHP:QHQ:PQ
This shows why the inductive definition of and can be
manipulated by tactics as we've been doing. We can also use it to
build proofs directly, using pattern-matching. For instance:
Definition and_comm'_aux P Q (H : P /\ Q) : Q /\ P := match H with | conj HP HQ => conj HQ HP end. Definition and_comm' P Q : P /\ Q <-> Q /\ P := conj (and_comm'_aux P Q) (and_comm'_aux Q P).
Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (conj_fact)
Admitted.forall P Q R : Prop, P /\ Q -> Q /\ R -> P /\ R
☐
(* ================================================================= *)
The inductive definition of disjunction uses two constructors, one
for each side of the disjunct:
Module Or. Inductive or (P Q : Prop) : Prop := | or_introl : P -> or P Q | or_intror : Q -> or P Q. End Or.
This declaration explains the behavior of the destruct tactic on
a disjunctive hypothesis, since the generated subgoals match the
shape of the or_introl and or_intror constructors.
Once again, we can also directly write proof objects for theorems
involving or, without resorting to tactics.
Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (or_commut'')
Admitted.forall P Q : Prop, P \/ Q -> Q \/ P
☐
(* ================================================================= *)
To give evidence for an existential quantifier, we package a
witness x together with a proof that x satisfies the property
P:
Module Ex. Inductive ex {A : Type} (P : A -> Prop) : Prop := | ex_intro : forall x : A, P x -> ex P. End Ex.
This may benefit from a little unpacking. The core definition is
for a type former ex that can be used to build propositions of
the form ex P, where P itself is a function from witness
values in the type A to propositions. The ex_intro
constructor then offers a way of constructing evidence for ex P,
given a witness x and a proof of P x.
The more familiar form ∃ x, P x desugars to an expression
involving ex:
Here's how to define an explicit proof object involving ex:
Definition some_nat_is_even : exists n, even n :=
ex_intro even 4 (ev_SS 2 (ev_SS 0 ev_0)).
Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (ex_ev_Sn)
Admitted.exists n : nat, even (S n)
☐
(* ================================================================= *)
The inductive definition of the True proposition is simple:
Inductive True : Prop :=
| I : True.
It has one constructor (so every proof of True is the same, so
being given a proof of True is not informative.)
False is equally simple -- indeed, so simple it may look
syntactically wrong at first glance!
Inductive False : Prop := .
That is, False is an inductive type with no constructors --
i.e., no way to build evidence for it.
End Props. (* ################################################################# *)
Even Coq's equality relation is not built in. It has the
following inductive definition. (Actually, the definition in the
standard library is a slight variant of this, which gives an
induction principle that is slightly easier to use.)
Module MyEquality. Inductive eq {X:Type} : X -> X -> Prop := | eq_refl : forall x, eq x x. Notation "x == y" := (eq x y) (at level 70, no associativity) : type_scope.
The way to think about this definition is that, given a set X,
it defines a family of propositions "x is equal to y,"
indexed by pairs of values (x and y) from X. There is just
one way of constructing evidence for members of this family:
applying the constructor eq_refl to a type X and a single
value x : X, which yields evidence that x is equal to x.
Other types of the form eq x y where x and y are not the
same are thus uninhabited.
We can use eq_refl to construct evidence that, for example, 2 =
2. Can we also use it to construct evidence that 1 + 1 = 2?
Yes, we can. Indeed, it is the very same piece of evidence!
The reason is that Coq treats as "the same" any two terms that are
convertible according to a simple set of computation rules.
These rules, which are similar to those used by Compute, include
evaluation of function application, inlining of definitions, and
simplification of matches.
2 + 2 == 1 + 3apply eq_refl. Qed.2 + 2 == 1 + 3
The reflexivity tactic that we have used to prove equalities up
to now is essentially just shorthand for apply eq_refl.
In tactic-based proofs of equality, the conversion rules are
normally hidden in uses of simpl (either explicit or implicit in
other tactics such as reflexivity).
But you can see them directly at work in the following explicit
proof objects:
Definition four' : 2 + 2 == 1 + 3 := eq_refl 4. Definition singleton : forall (X:Type) (x:X), []++[x] == x::[] := fun (X:Type) (x:X) => eq_refl [x].
Exercise: 2 stars, standard (equality__leibniz_equality)
forall (X : Type) (x y : X), x == y -> forall P : X -> Prop, P x -> P y(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.forall (X : Type) (x y : X), x == y -> forall P : X -> Prop, P x -> P y
☐
Exercise: 5 stars, standard, optional (leibniz_equality__equality)
forall (X : Type) (x y : X), (forall P : X -> Prop, P x -> P y) -> x == y(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.forall (X : Type) (x y : X), (forall P : X -> Prop, P x -> P y) -> x == y
☐
End MyEquality. (* ================================================================= *)
We've seen inversion used with both equality hypotheses and
hypotheses about inductively defined propositions. Now that we've
seen that these are actually the same thing, we're in a position
to take a closer look at how inversion behaves.
In general, the inversion tactic...
- takes a hypothesis H whose type P is inductively defined,
and
- for each constructor C in P's definition,
- generates a new subgoal in which we assume H was
built with C,
- adds the arguments (premises) of C to the context of
the subgoal as extra hypotheses,
- matches the conclusion (result type) of C against the
current goal and calculates a set of equalities that must
hold in order for C to be applicable,
- adds these equalities to the context (and, for convenience,
rewrites them in the goal), and
- if the equalities are not satisfiable (e.g., they involve things like S n = O), immediately solves the subgoal.
- generates a new subgoal in which we assume H was
built with C,
Example: If we invert a hypothesis built with or, there are
two constructors, so two subgoals get generated. The
conclusion (result type) of the constructor (P ∨ Q) doesn't
place any restrictions on the form of P or Q, so we don't get
any extra equalities in the context of the subgoal.
Example: If we invert a hypothesis built with and, there is
only one constructor, so only one subgoal gets generated. Again,
the conclusion (result type) of the constructor (P ∧ Q) doesn't
place any restrictions on the form of P or Q, so we don't get
any extra equalities in the context of the subgoal. The
constructor does have two arguments, though, and these can be seen
in the context in the subgoal.
Example: If we invert a hypothesis built with eq, there is
again only one constructor, so only one subgoal gets generated.
Now, though, the form of the eq_refl constructor does give us
some extra information: it tells us that the two arguments to eq
must be the same! The inversion tactic adds this fact to the
context.
(* Wed Jan 9 12:02:45 EST 2019 *)